Normativity and its vindicationsthe case of logic

  1. Martínez Vidal, Concepción
Revista:
Theoria: an international journal for theory, history and foundations of science

ISSN: 0495-4548

Ano de publicación: 2004

Volume: 19

Número: 50

Páxinas: 191-206

Tipo: Artigo

Outras publicacións en: Theoria: an international journal for theory, history and foundations of science

Resumo

Physical laws are irresistible. Logical rules are not. That is why logic is said to be normative. Given a system of logic we have a Norma, a standard of correctness. The problem is that we need another Norma to establish when the standard of correctness is to be applied. Subsequently we start by clarifying the senses in which the term "logic" and the term "normativity" are being used. Then we explore two different epistemologies for logic to see the sort of defence of the normativity of logic they allow for; if any. The analysis concentrates on the case of classical logic. In particular the issue will be appraised from the perspective put forward by the epistemology based on the methodology of wide reflective equilibrium and the scientific one underlying the view of logic as model.

Referencias bibliográficas

  • Burgess, J.P. (1992). "Proofs about proofs: a defense of classical logic", in M. Detlefsen, Proofs, Logic and Formalization. London and New York: Routledge
  • Corcoran, J. (1973). "Gaps between logical theory and mathematical practice", in M. Bunge (ed.), The Methodological Unity of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel
  • Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction and forecast. Cambridge (Mass.): Cambridge University Press
  • Jané, I. (in print). "Higher order Logic reconsidered", in S. Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook for the Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Korsgaard, Ch. (1996). The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
  • Martínez Vidal, C. (2001). "The view of logic as model: Comments on Stewart Shapiro's paper", Agora, 20, 1, pp. 175-179
  • - (in print). "The view of logic as model and the objectivity of logic"
  • Railton, P. (2000). "Normative force and normative freedom: Hume and Kant", in J. Dancy, Normativity. Oxford: Blackwell
  • Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press
  • Resnik, M. (1985). "Logic: normative or descriptive? The ethics of belief or a branch of psychology", Philosophy of Science, 52, pp. 221-238
  • - (1996). "Ought there to be but one logic?", in B.J. Copeland (ed.), Logic and Reality. Essays on the Legacy of Arthur Prior. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 489-517
  • - (1997). Mathematics as a Science of Patterns. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • - (2000). "Against logical realism", History and Philosophy of Logic, 20, 181-194
  • Shapiro, S. (2000), "The status of logic", in P. Boghossian and C. Peacocke (eds.), New essays on the A Priori. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 333-365
  • - (2000b). Philosophy of Mathematics. Structure and Ontology. New York: Oxford University Press
  • - (2002). "Modelling and normativity: How much revisionism can we tolerate?", Agora, 159-173
  • Thagard, P. (1982). "From the descriptive to the normative in psychology and logic", Philosophy of Science, 49, pp. 24-42
  • Wright, C. (1988). "Moral values, projection and secondary qualities", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, pp. 1-26
  • - (1992). Truth and Objectivity. London: Harvard University Press